-
Biography
-
Austin’s analysis of an utterance. The locution/illocution distinction
-
Searle’s response to Austin’s theory
-
Criticism of the theories
1 1.Biography
JohnLangshaw Austin (1911-1960) was born in Lancaster, England. He
studied Classics in Oxford, receiving a First in Classics and
Philosophy and went on to then become a Professor of Moral Philosophy
at the University of Oxford after serving in the war. His work has
covered a wide range of areas of philosophy, including knowledge,
perception, action, freedom, truth, language, and the use of language
in speech acts. What concerns us is the distinctions that Austin drew
in his work on speech acts—in particular his distinction between
locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts—, which has
assumed something like canonical status in more recent work. It is
possible to say that all the topics he investigated are intertwined
in his works, for it is from the relation between his view of truth
and language, which his theory of Speech Acts arises.
On
the other hand, John Searle, (1932-) is an American
philosopher who currently works as Professor of Philosophy at the
University of California, Berkley. He started his education at the
University of Wisconsin-Madison and then attended Oxford University,
where he completed his studies, and went on to work there. He is
mostly known for his work in the fields of philosophy of language,
philosophy of mind and social philosophy. He has received numerous
awards. Within the field of philosophy, he tried to synthesise the
ideas of other philosophers such as Austin and his ‘illocutionary
act’, but also ideas from Ludwig Wittgenstein or from Griece, so
that his work embraces ideas from many different authors. In his book
Speech Acts, published in 1969 he attempts to give his own
view on illocutionary act bearing in mind the ideas of these authors
among others.
2.
Austin’s analysis of an utterance. The locution/illocution
distinction
Austin
is usually correctly credited with founding Speech Act theory with
his How To Do Things With Words published in 1962. Austin’s
fundamental insight was that utterances not only say things but “do
things”.
Austin’s
analysis of an utterance
For
Austin, speech acts or illocutionary acts can be analysed on three
levels:
(1)
A locutionary act: the saying of an utterance (making noises
conforming to certain vocabulary and grammar)
(2)
An illocutionary act: the force of an utterance such as
informing, warning or undertaking (its intended significance as a
socially valid verbal action)
(3)
A perlocutionary act: the effect of an utterance, the action
performed by speaking. (persuading, convincing, scaring…) (Marc
Lloyd, 2007)
The
locution / illocution distinction
Austin
distinguished locution and illocution by pointing out that the same
locution (e.g., “I am coming back” ) could be used to perform a
number of different illocutions (e.g. stating, predicting, promising,
encouraging, warning, questioning). Searle rejected Austin’s
division between locution and illocution.
Performative
utterances
An
interesting type of illocutionary speech act is that performed in the
utterance of what Austin calls performatives, typical instances of
which are "I nominate John to be President", "I
sentence you to ten years' imprisonment", or "I promise to
pay you back." In these typical, rather explicit cases of
performative sentences, the action that the sentence describes
(nominating, sentencing, promising) is performed by the utterance of
the sentence itself.
Even
where Austin’s work has been challenged, rejected or revised, How
To Do Things With Words continues to attract attention and has
remained foundational and programmatic for speech act approaches to
language use.
3.
Searle’s response to Austin’s theory
Searle
rejected Austin’s division between locution and illocution, rightly
seeing that the meaning of an utterance is usually inextricably bound
up with its force.
Searle
suggested replacing Austin’s locution / illocution distinction with
the alternative distinction of:
(1)
utterance acts, in which the speaker utters words
(2)
propositional acts, in which the speaker refers and predicates
and
(3)
illocutionary acts, which have a particular force.
For
Searle, an illocutionary act is a function both of its propositional
content and its illocutionary force and can be expressed using the
notation F(p), where F is the force and p is the propositional
content of reference (R) and sense (S), p=RS.
Searle
introduced to speech act theory the analysis of the differences in
direction of fit between words and the world in different utterances.
This distinction considers whether a speaker attempts to conform his
words to the world (a word to world fit, as in statements,
descriptions, assertions or explanations) or the world to his words
(a world to word fit, as in requests, commands, vows and
promises). Though this is a useful distinction, it should be
noted that every utterance affects the world by itself becoming a new
fact in the world. Even if only the speaker hears his own word to
world statement, he is changed by having made it.
Without
a doubt, Searle’s work in this area has superseded Austin’s one.
His work in the classification of illocutionary acts is a significant
advance on Austin’s and has become the standard theory.
Searle
also described the psychological state in the speaker or sincerity
condition which is required for each type of illocutionary act, and
the propositional content involved.
Searle's
illocutionary acts
5
mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive classes:
-
Assertive- the speaker becomes committed to the truth of the propositional content. Example “it is raining”
-
Directive- the speaker tries to get the hearer to act in such a way as to fulfil what is represented by the propositional content. Example “Close the door”
-
Commissive- the speaker becomes committed to act in the way represented by the propositional content. Example promising, “I will finish the paper my tomorrow”
-
Expresive- the speaker simply expresses the sincerity of condition of the illocutionary act. Example: “I’m glad it is raining!”
-
Declarative- the speaker performs an action representing herself as performing that action. Example: “I name this ship Queen Elizabeth”
4.
Theories' criticism
The
speech act borrows its ideas from structuralism which claims that the
elements of the language are rather synchronic, they have the meaning
they are given at a certain point, they don't carry historical
meaning (diachronic)
While
most philosophers of language had examined the dennotative meaning
(the literal meaning)of words and the logic of propositions, Speech
Act Theorists focus on connotations and the instrumentality of
language.
Response
The
theory of speech acts has had a tremendous influence on
functional aspects of pragmatic theory but it has also received very
strong criticism. They
were criticised because:
1.
They based their theory only on acoustic and momentary communication
2.
They were only focussed on a very specific type of expressions and
did not watch the complete reality of the linguistic communication.
They didn't work on a theory of the communicative interaction
3.
Very simple verbal contexts in which they apply their theory
4.
Huge tendency for showing a very fragmented linguistic reality:
Weinrich in 1981 criticized that speech acts shouldn't help
linguistic to pack reality in boxes.
To
sum up, the main critique they received was that conversation is
not just a mere chain of independent illocutionary forces rather,
speech acts are related to other speech acts with a wider discourse
context. Speech act theory, in that it does not consider the function
played by utterances in driving conversation is, therefore,
insufficient in accounting for what actually happens in
conversation."
Enjoying
our presentation
No comments:
Post a Comment